翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ "O" Is for Outlaw
・ "O"-Jung.Ban.Hap.
・ "Ode-to-Napoleon" hexachord
・ "Oh Yeah!" Live
・ "Our Contemporary" regional art exhibition (Leningrad, 1975)
・ "P" Is for Peril
・ "Pimpernel" Smith
・ "Polish death camp" controversy
・ "Pro knigi" ("About books")
・ "Prosopa" Greek Television Awards
・ "Pussy Cats" Starring the Walkmen
・ "Q" Is for Quarry
・ "R" Is for Ricochet
・ "R" The King (2016 film)
・ "Rags" Ragland
・ ! (album)
・ ! (disambiguation)
・ !!
・ !!!
・ !!! (album)
・ !!Destroy-Oh-Boy!!
・ !Action Pact!
・ !Arriba! La Pachanga
・ !Hero
・ !Hero (album)
・ !Kung language
・ !Oka Tokat
・ !PAUS3
・ !T.O.O.H.!
・ !Women Art Revolution


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Kant : ウィキペディア英語版
Immanuel Kant

| death_place = Königsberg, Prussia
| residence = Königsberg, Prussia
| nationality = Prussian
| region = Western philosophy
| era = 18th-century philosophy
| main_interests =
| school_tradition =
| notable_ideas =
| influences =
| influenced =
| signature = Immanuel Kant signature.svg
}}
Immanuel Kant (;〔("Kant" ). ''Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary''.〕 ; 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher who is considered the central figure of modern philosophy. Kant argued that fundamental concepts of the human mind structure human experience, that reason is the source of morality, that aesthetics arises from a faculty of disinterested judgment, that space and time are forms of our understanding, and that the world as it is "in-itself" is unknowable. Kant took himself to have effected a Copernican revolution in philosophy, akin to Copernicus' reversal of the age-old belief that the sun revolved around the earth. His beliefs continue to have a major influence on contemporary philosophy, especially the fields of metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, political theory, and aesthetics.
Kant in his critical phase sought to 'reverse' the orientation of pre-critical philosophy by showing how the traditional problems of metaphysics can be overcome by supposing that the agreement between reality and the concepts we use to conceive it arises not because our mental concepts have come to passively mirror reality, but because reality must conform to the human mind's active concepts to be conceivable and at all possible for us to experience. Kant thus regarded the basic categories of the human mind as the transcendental "condition of possibility" for any experience.
Politically, Kant was one of the earliest exponents of the idea that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and international cooperation. He believed that this eventually will be the outcome of universal history, although it is not rationally planned.〔Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose.〕 The exact nature of Kant's religious ideas continue to be the subject of especially heated philosophical dispute, with viewpoints ranging from the idea that Kant was an early and radical exponent of atheism who finally exploded the ontological argument for God's existence, to more critical treatments epitomized by Nietzsche who claimed that Kant had "theologian blood"〔https://books.google.com/books?id=DcVl57jzP2gC&pg=PA9&lpg=PA9&dq=%22theologian+blood%22+the+antichrist&source=bl&ots=CzqxPveANg&sig=A-X36l8mmYUUI3wT56qpkBnVwpc&hl=en&sa=X&ved=0CCwQ6AEwA2oVChMIm-iS_d_UxwIVA3Y-Ch2mGgvo#v=onepage&q=%22theologian%20blood%22%20the%20antichrist&f=false〕 and that Kant was merely a sophisticated apologist for traditional Christian religious belief, writing that "Kant wanted to prove, in a way that would dumbfound the common man, that the common man was right: that was the secret joke of this soul."〔http://www.fed.cuhk.edu.hk/~lchang/material/Evolutionary/Developmental/Greene-KantSoul.pdf〕
In Kant's major work, the ''Critique of Pure Reason'' (''Kritik der reinen Vernunft'', 1781), he attempted to explain the relationship between reason and human experience and to move beyond the failures of traditional philosophy and metaphysics. Kant wanted to put an end to an era of futile and speculative theories of human experience, while resisting the skepticism of thinkers such as David Hume. Kant regarded himself as ending and showing the way beyond the impasse which modern philosophy had led to between rationalists and empiricists, and is widely held to have synthesized these two early modern traditions in his thought.〔http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant/quote|"He synthesized early modern rationalism and empiricism"〕
Kant argued that our experiences are structured by necessary features of our minds. In his view, the mind shapes and structures experience so that, on an abstract level, all human experience shares certain essential structural features. Among other things, Kant believed that the concepts of ''space'' and ''time'' are integral to all human experience, as are our concepts of ''cause'' and ''effect''.〔
〕 One important consequence of this view is that our experience of things is always of the ''phenomenal'' world as conveyed by our senses: we do not have direct access to things in themselves, the so-called ''noumenal'' world. Kant published other important works on ethics, religion, law, aesthetics, astronomy, and history. These included the ''Critique of Practical Reason'' (''Kritik der praktischen Vernunft'', 1788), the ''Metaphysics of Morals'' (''Die Metaphysik der Sitten'', 1797), which dealt with ethics, and the ''Critique of Judgment'' (''Kritik der Urteilskraft'', 1790), which looks at aesthetics and teleology.
Kant aimed to resolve disputes between empirical and rationalist approaches. The former asserted that all knowledge comes through experience; the latter maintained that reason and innate ideas were prior. Kant argued that experience is purely subjective without first being processed by pure reason. He also said that using reason without applying it to experience only leads to theoretical illusions. The free and proper exercise of reason by the individual was a theme both of the Age of Enlightenment, and of Kant's approaches to the various problems of philosophy. His ideas influenced many thinkers in Germany during his lifetime, and he moved philosophy beyond the debate between the rationalists and empiricists.
==Biography==
Immanuel Kant was born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia (since 1946 the city of Kaliningrad, Kaliningrad Oblast, Russia). His mother, Anna Regina Reuter (1697–1737), was born in Nuremberg.〔
Kant's mother's name is sometimes erroneously given as Anna Regina Porter.
〕 His father, Johann Georg Kant (1682–1746), was a German harness maker from Memel, at the time Prussia's most northeastern city (now Klaipėda, Lithuania). Kant's paternal grandfather, Hans Kant,〔

had emigrated from Scotland to East Prussia, and his father still spelled their family name "Cant".〔http://www.csudh.edu/phenom_studies/western/lect_9.html〕 Kant was the fourth of nine children (four of them reached adulthood).〔http://www.freunde-kants.com/attachments/article/137/Bohnenrede%202015%20(de).pdf〕 Baptized 'Emanuel', he changed his name to 'Immanuel'〔Kuehn, Manfred. ''Kant: a Biography''. Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 26〕 after learning Hebrew.
Young Kant was a solid, albeit unspectacular, student. He was brought up in a Pietist household that stressed religious devotion, humility, and a literal interpretation of the Bible. His education was strict, punitive and disciplinary, and focused on Latin and religious instruction over mathematics and science.〔
Biographical information sourced from: Kuehn, Manfred. ''Kant: a Biography''. Cambridge University Press, 2001. ISBN 0-521-49704-3 the standard biography of Kant in English.
〕 Despite his religious upbringing and maintaining a belief in God, Kant was skeptical of religion in later life; various commentators have labelled him agnostic.〔"While this sounds skeptical, Kant is only agnostic about our knowledge of metaphysical objects such as God. And, as noted above, Kant's agnosticism leads to the conclusion that we can neither affirm nor deny claims made by traditional metaphysics." Andrew Fiala, J. M. D. Meiklejohn, ''Critique of Pure Reason'' – Introduction, page xi.
〕〔
〕〔
〕〔
〕〔
〕〔

Common myths about Kant's personal mannerisms are listed, explained, and refuted in Goldthwait's introduction to his translation of ''Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime''.〔
Kant, Immanuel. ''Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime''. Trans. John T. Goldthwait. University of California Press, 1961, 2003. ISBN 0-520-24078-2
〕 It is often held that Kant lived a very strict and disciplined life, leading to an oft-repeated story that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks. He never married, but seemed to have a rewarding social life — he was a popular teacher and a modestly successful author even before starting on his major philosophical works.
A common myth is that Kant never traveled more than from Königsberg his whole life.〔Lewis, Rick. 2005. 'Kant 200 Years On'. ''Philosophy Now''. No. 49.〕 In fact, between 1750 and 1754 he worked as a tutor (''Hauslehrer'') in Judtschen〔(Karl Vorländer: Immanuel Kant - Bei Pfarrer Andersch in Judtschen )〕 (now Veselovka, Russia, approximately 20 km) and in Groß-Arnsdorf〔(Karl Vorländer: Immanuel Kant - Bei Pfarrer Andersch in Judtschen )〕 (now Jarnołtowo near Morąg (germ. Mohrungen), Poland, approximately 145 km).

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Immanuel Kant」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.